极速赛车168官网 immaterial – Strange Notions https://strangenotions.com A Digital Areopagus // Reason. Faith. Dialogue. Mon, 01 Dec 2014 14:15:53 +0000 en-US hourly 1 https://wordpress.org/?v=6.7.1 极速赛车168官网 The Key Divine Attributes of the Absolutely Unique and Simple Unconditioned Reality https://strangenotions.com/the-key-divine-attributes-of-the-absolutely-unique-and-simple-unconditioned-reality/ https://strangenotions.com/the-key-divine-attributes-of-the-absolutely-unique-and-simple-unconditioned-reality/#comments Mon, 01 Dec 2014 14:15:53 +0000 http://strangenotions.com/?p=4733 Coffee

NOTE: Today we continue our six-part series by Karlo Broussard on a metaphysical proof for God's existence. The posts will run each of the next three Mondays:

 


 
Over the course of several posts we’ve been examining a metaphysical demonstration for God’s existence that has led us to conclude that there must exist one and only one unconditioned reality in all of reality, and that such a reality is absolutely simple in the metaphysical sense (reality that is pure being or pure existence). In the current post, I intend to further our argument that unconditioned reality is worthy of the term “God,” as classically defined, by laying out key divine attributes for this absolutely simple and unique unconditioned reality.

The first key attribute is that the unconditioned reality is the continuous creator of all else that is. We can begin by recalling what we’ve seen in part 1 of this metaphysical proof and that is the fact that every conditioned reality, in order to exist right here and right now, must ultimately have its conditions fulfilled by at least one unconditioned reality; otherwise the particular conditioned reality under consideration, say a cat, would not exist. It is in this sense that we can call such an unconditioned reality a Creator – it ultimately fulfills the conditions that a conditioned reality depends upon for its existence (it is the ultimate source of the conditioned reality’s being). This is in contrast to the more restricted or narrower sense of a creative agent that is responsible for the creation of the universe from nothing at some point in the finite past.

Now, since there can be only one unconditioned reality (as proven in the third installment of this series), it follows that every other existing thing is a conditioned reality, which means that in order for it to exist right here and right now, it would ultimately have to have its conditions fulfilled by the one unconditioned reality. Therefore, at every moment one could say that a conditioned reality (e.g., a cat) exists, that conditioned reality would owe its existence to the one unconditioned reality. Hence, the Creator (the unique, absolutely simple, and unconditioned reality) must be the continuous Creator (the ultimate source of fulfillment of conditions) of all else that is real at every moment it exists. This is the rationale behind the popular phrase, “If God would stop thinking about us, we would lapse into nothingness.”

The second key attribute is that of immutability (the inability to change). Change, as defined in the Aristotelian-Scholastic tradition, is simply the actualization of a potential within a being. For example, the cold tea that’s been sitting on my desk all afternoon has the potential to become hot and when I put it in the microwave or on the stove to re-heat it that potential will be made actual. As you read this article, you have the potential to learn something about change. Hopefully upon completing this article, you will have actualized that potential and thus will have experienced a growth in knowledge, i.e., change.

Now, every instance of change requires a changer (there must exist something that brings about the change). To use our previous example, the cold tea becomes hot due to the electromagnetic radiation in the microwave or the heat on the stove. Such a principle is not merely derived from our experiential knowledge of examples, like the tea getting hot, but from the very nature of change itself, which, recall, is the actualization of some potential. The tea’s potential to become hot cannot be actualized without something already actual precisely because the hotness of the tea is a mere potential when it is cold.

Furthermore, that which actualizes the tea’s potential for hotness would have to be something other than the tea itself. It could not actualize its own potential for hotness because in such a case it would have to be actually hot prior to actualizing the potential to become hot. In other words, it would have to be actually hot and potentially hot in the same respect at the same place and time. Obviously this amounts to an intrinsic contradiction and thus cannot be true. Therefore, the tea’s potential to become hot can only be actualized by something already actual and that something must be something other than the tea itself.

In light of this understanding of change, there are two ways in which we can see why the unconditioned reality cannot change.

First, if the one unconditioned reality could change, then that would mean it would depend upon something outside itself to actualize its potential, in which case an aspect of its being would be conditioned by that actualizer. But the unconditioned reality cannot have any aspect of its being that is conditioned by something outside itself for the simple reason that it is unconditioned reality. Therefore, the unconditioned reality cannot change.

The second line of reason that precludes mutability for the unconditioned reality involves its absolute simplicity (or the fact that it is pure being or pure existence without any real or really possible incompatible state of being on the same level of simplicity). According to the Aristotelian-Scholastic tradition, something that is pure being or pure existence is that which is purely actual. The reason is that something is in act in as much as it exists. To return to our previous example, the state of hotness for the tea did not exist until the heat on the stove made it actual. Grant it the potential for hotness was present in the tea in a way that other potentials are not (such as the potential to become a dragon) but it was not there actually while the tea was still cold. Therefore, existence and actuality are interchangeable. So, if unconditioned reality is pure existence then it must be pure actuality.

Now, something lacks potentiality in as much as it is in act. The cold tea has the potential for hotness but lacks or loses that potential when it becomes actually hot. So, if unconditioned reality is pure actuality, then it would be devoid of all potentiality – that is to say there is no aspect of being that a purely actual being can potentially acquire or lose.

Now, if change involves the actualization of some potential, and unconditioned reality has no potentiality whatsoever, then it logically follows that unconditioned reality cannot be subject to change. Therefore, the unconditioned reality is immutable.

The next attribute for consideration is eternality (atemporality or timelessness). There are two ways in which we can argue for this attribute.

The first is by way of absolute simplicity. Recall how we saw in the previous post on the absolute uniqueness of unconditioned reality that unconditioned reality cannot be restricted in its mode of existence by a temporal restriction – making it exist now instead of then. As was proven, such an intrinsic restriction for unconditioned reality would allow for a real or really possible incompatible state of being on the same level of simplicity that would be excluded from it. But as was also proven unconditioned reality cannot have any real or really possible incompatible states of being on the same level of simplicity that would be excluded from it less we end up with an intrinsic contradiction. Therefore, the unconditioned reality cannot be limited in its mode of existence by a temporal restriction. In other words, it cannot be conditioned by time; thus it must be eternal.

The second way to argue for the eternality of the unconditioned reality is from the attribute of immutability. We know from our experience and reason that mutability (or changeability) is an essential element of time. Anything existing in time goes from one point in time to another – your act of reading the words in the previous clause has now become your past (there has been a change). But as proven above the unconditioned reality cannot change. Therefore, the unconditioned reality cannot be conditioned by time in any sense but must exist outside of time altogether – it neither comes to be nor passes away – it cannot have any successive moments in its existence whatsoever. This is the essence of eternality.

Now, the argument for the attribute of immateriality follows a very similar line of reason as does the argument for eternality.

First, if the unconditioned reality was restricted in its mode of existence by matter, then it would be restricted by a spatial restriction since all matter has extension in space – it would exist here instead of there. Now, such an intrinsic restriction would allow for a real or really possible incompatible state of being that would be excluded from it. But recall that the unconditioned reality cannot have any real or really possible incompatible states of being on the same level of simplicity that would be excluded from it less we end up with an intrinsic contradiction. Therefore, the unconditioned reality cannot be restricted in its mode of existence by a spatial restriction. And if the unconditioned reality cannot be restricted by a spatial restriction, then it cannot be restricted by matter. In other words, it must be immaterial.

Furthermore, like eternality, the second argument for immateriality comes from the immutability of the unconditioned reality. We know from our experience and from reason that all material things are subject to change. The reason is that all material things have potentiality built into them. The tree has the potential to be cut down; it’s wood to be made into paper. My body has the potential to break down into its component parts and become dust in the grave. The hot tea has the potential to become cool. So, everything that is material is subject to change. But, as proven above, the unconditioned reality is immutable. Therefore, the unconditioned reality must be immaterial.

So, along with the key attributes of absolute simplicity and uniqueness (discussed in the previous posts of this series), unconditioned reality is also immutable, eternal, immaterial, and the continuous creator of all else that is. This surely fits the traditional description of “God.”

But is there more? Can we go further in deducing key attributes for the one unconditioned reality that have been classically ascribed to God? The answer is yes. In the next post for this series, I will consider the absolute perfection of the one unconditioned reality along with the three “omnis” – omnibenevolence, omnipotence, and omniscience.
 
 
(Image credit: Unsplash)

]]>
https://strangenotions.com/the-key-divine-attributes-of-the-absolutely-unique-and-simple-unconditioned-reality/feed/ 66
极速赛车168官网 Does the Immaterial Exist? https://strangenotions.com/does-immaterial-exist/ https://strangenotions.com/does-immaterial-exist/#comments Wed, 31 Jul 2013 12:56:10 +0000 http://strangenotions.com/?p=3516 Cows

One common arguments from atheists is that matter is all there is, and that the immaterial (God, angels, the human soul, etc.) simply doesn't exist. This position is generally called “philosophical materialism,” although that term encompasses a number of distinct positions. In any case, here’s one of the clearest presentations of this argument:
 

"When we speak of immaterial things, we are speaking of something that has no physical substance. Now, if you think about this, everything we know to exist has physical properties. Your arm, leg, mind, blood, teeth, tongue, and everything else are physical. They are in the form of your physical body. Your brain can’t work without physical/material processes of chemistry and electricity. Electricity can’t work without the physical electrons. A windmill can’t work without the physical air that passes across its blades. Everything we know to exist is physical. [….]
 
So, if God is not material, what is God? If there is no answer for what God is, all we can say is God doesn't exist, or he exists nowhere and is comprised of nothing, which I don’t see how that isn't the same exact thing. It is rather interesting how the theist description of what there God is actually puts their God out of existence."

 
Or, a shorter version of essentially the same argument:
 

"If we are talking about immaterial existence, then there is nothing to differentiate an entity or "thing" which exists from one which does not exist."

 
Often (including in the second link provided), these discussions descend into debates over speculative science: whether or not dark energy or photons have mass, etc. But I think that this materialist argument can be answered easily, using agreed-upon evidence. In other words, the fact that the universe is made up of something other than matter is self-evident, and should be admitted by anyone, upon close reflection. In addition to matter, we also see immaterial forms that can dictate the nature and behavior of the matter itself.

We can observe forms in nature, and cannot account for them in purely material ways. This is true even of forms that cannot exist apart from matter.  Consider the following examples, from most to least technical:
 
1. Isomers: This is my favorite example. When two or more (different) compounds share the same molecular formula, you have isomers. For example, there are three different compounds with the molecular formula C3H8O: methoxyethane (a colorless gas that is extremely flammable and reactive); propanol (a liquid solvent used in the pharmaceutical industry); and isopropyl alcohol (rubbing alcohol).

These are different substances, with different chemical properties. Yet these differences are not material. They’re formal. That is, each of the three substances is made up of the identical atoms: three carbon, right hydrogen, and one oxygen. It is the arrangement of those molecules that determines whether the substance will be methoxyethanepropanol, or rubbing alcohol. The same matter, in different forms, produces different substances.

2. Phase Changes: A more obvious example of this would be the phase changes of water. Depending on its form (solid, liquid, or gaseous), it exhibits different properties, and is structured differently. Yet it maintains the same molecular and structural formula.

3. Surfaces: The surface of a table is not the table itself. Surfaces are immaterial, and have no mass, and occupy no three-dimensional space. If you doubt this, try to imagine a surface that is three feet deep. Whatever you are visualizing is not a surface, but a substance with surfaces of its own. But we can still observe that surfaces exist.

4. Shapes: Envision two different objects of equal mass, made of identical materials. The first is a wooden cube, and the second is a wooden sphere. The difference between the two objects wouldn't be material, but formal.
 
In each of these cases, the form itself is immaterial. To test this, take your wooden objects, and remove the matter that they have in common (the wood). Likewise, take your isomers, and remove the matter that they have in common (the carbon, hydrogen, and oxygen). The result will be the same: you will be left with nothing. But does that mean that the different objects were, in fact, the same? Of course not. It means only that, in each of these cases, differences exist between the substances, but these differences cannot be isolated by removing the material common to each. That’s because these differences are immaterial, rather than material.

Those cases are obvious enough. A less obvious, but dramatically more important, example of a perceivable form is life itself. Consider what philosopher Dr. Peter Kreeft fittingly named the “Dead Cow Argument”: imagine you come across two cows--one that is alive, and one that has just died. What is the difference between these two cows? Craig Payne, quoting Kreeft, explains:
 

"There appears to be no material difference (e.g., in size or weight or color) between the two cows. Yet something is clearly missing. What is it?” The obvious answer is that the cow is “clearly missing” its life – its “soul” or anima, in other words, its animating principle or form, that which causes the cow to live and develop as a cow."

 
So the living and the dead cow, at this point, are still materially identical. Nevertheless, we can immediately observe that an immaterial difference exists, and a radically important one. As Kreeft notes, both cows have air in their lungs, but only one can breathe. This distinction is, as noted above, the “animating” principle of the matter: the form enabling a particular material substance to live. It is from this that we have the simplest understanding of what a soul is: the animating principle of a body.

Certainly, this is only the beginning of a discussion on the soul, not the end. We’re still left to determine what sort of a thing the immaterial soul is, whether a human soul is like a cow soul, and so on.  But this line of reasoning does dispel the notion that the material is all that there is.
 
 
Originally published at Shameless Popery. Used with author's permission.
(Image credit: Coleman Report)

]]>
https://strangenotions.com/does-immaterial-exist/feed/ 473